GOVT 345 Quiz 6
GOVT 345 Quiz 6 Liberty University
GOVT 345 Quiz 6: Justice and Rights
Covers the Learn material from Module 6: Week 6.
- Pareto optimality has been reached if and when any further alteration would result in a person being worse off.
- In Plato’s conception of justice, the appetitive rules over the spirited which rules over the rational.
- Some economists argue that the common law is not only efficient but that it is the common law because it is efficient.
- Economic analysis of the law is where economics, law, and justice meet.
- Nozick fails to explain how the wealthy are to be prevented from gaining and using power to further their position.
- In Aristotle’s lexicon, universal justice meant a person is acting lawfully and fairly.
- Pareto efficiency means that those proting from a transaction have enough to compensate those who lose.
- As a general rule, Aristotle’s virtue requires complying with law because law encourage citizens to act virtuously.
- Aristotle divided justice into universal and particular justice. The latter could be further subdivided into distributive and rectificatory justice.
- For Kant, any action that you would be willing to impose universally is inherently good and consistent with justice.
- The concept of animal rights can easily dismissed: since they have no duties, animals can have no rights.
- In the Hohfeldian system, first order rights are those one exercises over your second order rights.
- In the Hohfeldian system, the presence of a claim means there is corresponding duty.
- A positive right essentially grants the holder a right to receive and thus places a duty upon another to provide.
- Rectificatory justice rectifies incorrect distributions.
- The Interest Theory says humans have interests, a right to further those interests, and that protecting those interests is part of the pursuit of the good life.
- Q. Adams’ statement, “Duty is ours, results are God’s” is a consequentialist statement.
- Natural rights are tangible and contingent on some other law.
- Act utilitarianism judges a rule by the consequences of compliance with the rule.
- Utilitarianism is inherently deontological.
Other sets
- The Interest Theory says humans have interests, a right to further those interests, and that protecting those interests is part of the pursuit of the good life.
- The Interest Theory of Rights sees man as a small sovereign imposing duties on others.
- For a natural lawyer, a legal right emerges from a moral right which emerges from a natural right.
- In Aristotle’s lexicon, universal justice meant a person is acting lawfully and fairly.
- Nozick fails to explain how the wealthy are to be prevented from gaining and using power to further their position.
- “I must study to pass the exam” is a hypothetical imperative because the duty springs from the purpose.
- One desirable aspect of the felicific calculous is that it not only takes into account a rise in pleasure but also in how evenly that pleasure is distributed among the public in general.
- One significant problem with utilitarianism is that it treats people as a means to an end.
- You have a privilege to use your property and the power to grant that privilege to another.
- A positive right essentially grants the holder a right to receive and thus places a duty upon another to provide.
- A major criticism of Rawls is that his theory of justice cannot be justice since it is not about giving people their just deserts.
- For Kant, any action that you would be willing to impose universally is inherently good and consistent with justice.
- Kant’s central inquiry is—“Would I will that all act in this manner?”
- As a general rule, Aristotle’s virtue requires complying with law because law encourage citizens to act virtuously.
- The rights-, duty-, and goal-based categories are mutually exclusive. Choosing one means abandoning the other.
- A moral right is enforceable even if there is no corresponding legal right.
- Some economists argue that the common law is not only efficient but that it is the common law because it is efficient.
- Posner says hard cases are adjudicated so as to maximize wealth.
- Q. Adams’ statement, “Duty is ours, results are God’s” is a consequentialist statement.
- In the Hohfeldian system, the presence of a claim means there is corresponding duty.
Other sets
- The concept of animal rights can easily dismissed: since they have no duties, animals can have no rights.
- You have a privilege to use your property and the power to grant that privilege to another.
- A moral right is enforceable even if there is no corresponding legal right.
- Act utilitarianism judges an act in light of the consequences of that act.
- Bentham would agree with Posner—the common law is definitely efficient.
- Distributive justice means people receiving what they merit.
- Economic analysis of the law is where economics, law, and justice meet.
- In Plato’s conception of justice, the appetitive rules over the spirited which rules over the rational.
- Active rights refer to Hohfeld’s claim and immunity.
- The Interest Theory of Rights sees man as a small sovereign imposing duties on others.
- Immunity in the Hohfeldian system refers to the ability to prevent others from altering your claim.
- The rights-, duty-, and goal-based categories are mutually exclusive. Choosing one means abandoning the other.
- Some economists argue that the common law is not only efficient but that it is the common law because it is efficient.
- Utilitarianism is inherently deontological.
- The source of a legal right is a positive law.
- Posner says hard cases are adjudicated so as to maximize wealth.
- “Let justice be done though the heavens fall” is a deontological statement.
- In Aristotle’s lexicon, universal justice meant a person is acting lawfully and fairly.
- Pareto efficiency means that those profiting from a transaction have enough to compensate those who lose.
- Aristotle divided justice into universal and particular justice. The latter could be further subdivided into distributive and rectificatory justice.
Other sets
Set 1
- For Aristotle justice requires obedience to laws whether just or not.
- Utilitarianism is inherently deontological.
- The Interest Theory of Rights sees man as a small sovereign imposing duties on others.
- The Coase theorem says that where there are zero transaction costs, the efficient outcome will occur regardless of the choice of legal rule.
- Nozick fails to explain how the wealthy are to be prevented from gaining and using power to further their position.
- Kant’s central inquiry is—“Would I will that all act in this manner?”
- The Will and Interest Theories do not necessarily correlate to particular schools of jurisprudence.
- Rectificatory justice rectifies incorrect distributions.
- Deontology includes an examination of the possible consequences.
- Distributive justice means people receiving what they merit.
- In Aristotle’s lexicon, universal justice meant a person is acting lawfully and fairly.
- In the Hohfeldian system, first order rights are those one exercises over your second order rights.
- “Let justice be done though the heavens fall” is a deontological statement.
- The source of a legal right is a positive law.
- “I must study to pass the exam” is a hypothetical imperative because the duty springs from the purpose.
- A major criticism of Rawls is that his theory of justice cannot be justice since it is not about giving people their just deserts.
- The Interest Theory says humans have interests, a right to further those interests, and that protecting those interests is part of the pursuit of the good life.
- Opposition to torture based on concern for national reputation is a duty-based argument.
- For a natural lawyer, a legal right emerges from a moral right which emerges from a natural right.
- Robert Nozick is known for his “Justice as Fairness” theory which he claims is the only way to preserve individual liberty.
Set 2
- “I must study to pass the exam” is a hypothetical imperative because the duty springs from the purpose.
- In Aristotle’s lexicon, universal justice meant a person is acting lawfully and fairly.
- Kant’s central inquiry is—“Would I will that all act in this manner?”
- Utilitarianism is inherently deontological.
- The Interest Theory of Rights sees man as a small sovereign imposing duties on others.
- Active rights refer to Hohfeld’s claim and immunity.
- John Rawls is known for his free-market libertarian perspective on rights and justice.
- The Interest Theory says humans have interests, a right to further those interests, and that protecting those interests is part of the pursuit of the good life.
- One desirable aspect of the felicific calculous is that it not only takes into account a rise in pleasure but also in how evenly that pleasure is distributed among the public in general.
- A moral right is enforceable even if there is no corresponding legal right.
- A major criticism of Rawls is that his theory of justice cannot be justice since it is not about giving people their just deserts.
- The concept of animal rights can easily dismissed: since they have no duties, animals can have no rights.
- Nozick fails to explain how the wealthy are to be prevented from gaining and using power to further their position.
- Robert Nozick is known for his “Justice as Fairness” theory which he claims is the only way to preserve individual liberty.
- Rectificatory justice rectifies incorrect distributions.
- Opposition to torture based on concern for national reputation is a duty-based argument.
- Aristotle divided justice into universal and particular justice. The latter could be further subdivided into distributive and rectificatory justice.
- Pareto efficiency means that those profiting from a transaction have enough to compensate those who lose.
- In the Hohfeldian system, first order rights are those one exercises over your second order rights.
- Hypothetical imperatives are unconditional oughts such as “do not steal”.